Eliminating stupidity is easier than creating brilliance
Is poker a game of pure luck, or is there skill involved too?
One way to test, as Steve Levitt suggested, is to check if it's possible to lose on purpose. If it is, then there must be skill involved, because the player has some control of the outcome. And, of course, it *is* possible to lose at poker at will, if you want to ... so it's reasonable to argue that poker is a game of skill.
On the other hand, you can't lose the lottery on purpose, no matter how hard you try. So, the lottery is just a game of luck.
But ... there are exceptions to the "lose on purpose" rule.
An easy one is tic-tac-toe. It's easy to lose on purpose -- just go second, and take a side square when it's your turn. The first player, assuming he plays his best, is certain to beat you. On the other hand, you can't *win* on purpose. If both competitors play optimally, the result will always be a draw.
If you don't like that one, try casino blackjack. You can lose on purpose just by hitting every hand -- eventually, you'll go over 21 and bust. But, can you *win* on purpose? Only to a certain limit. If you aren't a card counter, the best you can do is to faithfully follow "basic strategy." In that case, you'll reduce the house advantage to its minimum possible value -- 0.5% -- which means that you'll lose, on average, $1 for every $200 you bet. Any deviation from that will be random luck.
That is: you can lose as much as you want, on purpose. But you can't win any more than the best of the other players, on purpose.
Even though blackjack passes the "lose on purpose" rule, I think most people would argue that it's a game of luck. Even though you can lose on purpose, there's no way to *win* on purpose ... that is, there's no way to beat the best players by improving your skill.
------
Why is this, that you can lose on purpose, but you can't win on purpose? In this case, it's deliberate, human-caused. When we invent games of skill, we keep the ones that have an interesting struggle to win. We don't care whether there's a struggle to lose, because, who cares? The object is to win.
Or, you can look at it this way. When there's competition for a goal, it's hard to win, because you have to beat your opponent, who's trying just as hard as you. When there's no competition for a goal -- like losing -- it's easy, because nobody is trying to prevent you.
If everyone is trying for X, it's hard to be the most X. But it's easy to be the most "not X".
------
This seems like it doesn't matter much, but ... there are interesting consequences. Let's suppose that you're a baseball team, and you're trying to decide who to draft. There are 29 other teams competing with you to make the best choice, but nobody competing with you to make the worst choice.
That means it's hard to beat the other teams on purpose. But it's easy to lose to the other teams on purpose -- just pick your mother, for instance.
Now, the interesting part. The same thing applies about winning and losing by accident. It's hard to *beat* the other teams by accident, but it's easy to *lose* to the other teams by accident.
Suppose you scout a player, and you think he's the next Mike Trout. The other teams are scouting him too. If you're right about him, and the other teams are too, the only way you're going to get him is if you have the first draft choice. Otherwise, some other team will snap him up before you.
But ... suppose he's *not* the next Mike Trout. You just happened to see him on a day he went 5-for-5 with three home runs. He's really just a fourth round pick, and you've badly overrated him. What happens? You inevitably draft him too high, and you suffer. You've lost by "accident". By mistake. By lack of skill.
It's hard to win by intention, fluke, or skill -- but it's easy to lose by intention, fluke, or (lack of) skill.
------
Let's suppose your scouting department concentrates on a few players. It spends substantial time analyzing those players, and it usually does OK evaulating them.
There's a player named Andrew. The MLB consensus is that he's going to be the 20th pick. Your scouts spent a lot of time on him, and they think he's better than that. Their opinion is that he's actually the 9th best player in the draft.
There's another player named Bob. MLB thinks he's the 16th best player. Your scouts think he's only the 30th best.
The draft comes along, and you have pick number 16. How much benefit do you gain from all that intelligence gathering? Suppose, if you like, that your scouts are absolutely correct, that they have the players ranked perfectly.
Well, if Andrew is available when your turn comes along, you snap him up for a gain of "7" spots. But that's not guaranteed, because, after all, you're not the only team doing scouting! If any one of the teams drafting from 9th to 15th came to the same conclusion, they've already grabbed him. In that case, your benefit from all that scouting winds up being ... zero.
What if Bob is available when your turn comes along? Well, you're going to pass on him, because you know he's not that good. But, if you hadn't done the scouting, you would have taken him with your number sixteen pick. You would have had a loss of "14" spots.
In the case of Bob, your intelligence *did* help you. It helped you a lot. And, it doesn't matter if other teams scouted him. Even if every other team reached the same conclusion you did, you've *still* saved yourself a big mistake by scouting him too. If you hadn't scouted him, you would have made a big mistake.
The moral: you gain more by not being stupid, than you do by being smart. Smart gets neutralized by other smart people. Stupid does not.
-------
If you're still not convinced, try this. I gather 10 people, and show them a jar that contains $1, $5, $20, and $100 bills in equal proportions. I pull one out, at random, so nobody can see, and I auction it off. The bidding will probably top out at around $31.50, which is the value of the average bill.
I do it again, but, this time, I'm not that careful, and you get a glimpse of the bill. So does Susan, the stranger sitting next to you.
What happens?
Well, if it's a $100 bill, you and Susan bid up the price to $99.99. Neither of you really benefit.
But, if it's a $1 bill ... neither you nor Susan bids. Each of you would have had a 1-in-10 chance of paying $31.50 for the bill and suffering a loss of $30.50. On an expected value basis, each of you gained $3.05 from your secret knowledge.
------
As I said at the Sloan Conference -- well, I don't remember saying it, but someone else said I did -- "one of the things that analytics can do really well is filter out the really stupid decisions."
What I was probably thinking, was something like this: If the 1980 Expos had had a sabermetrics department, they could have spent hours trying to squeeze out a couple of extra runs by lineup management ... but they would have been much, much better off figuring out that Rodney Scott's offense was so bad, he shouldn't have been a starter.
It works that way in your personal life, too. You can spend a lot of time and money picking out the perfect floral bouquet for your date ... but you're probably better off checking if you have bad breath and taking the porn out of the glove compartment.
-------
If it's true that sabermetrics helps teams win, I'd bet that at most of the benefit comes from the "negative" side: having a framework that flags bad decisions before they get made.
And that's why, if I owned a professional sports team, that would be my priority for my sabermetrics department. First, concentrate on eliminating bad decisions, not on making good decisions better. And, second, figure out what everyone else knows, but we don't.
8 Comments:
I was explaining this to my kids a few weeks ago. You can ruin your credit score or reputation very easily and quickly compared to the time it takes to restore them. Seems this lesson is incredibly portable.
I completely agree with your premise about elimination being easier than creating brilliance (I don't share links, but if you're willing to google "what's your david" "slate consulting", you'll see an article I wrote with a similar idea).
Your exceptions to Steven Levitt's rule aren't exceptions though and I'd bet the appearance that they are exceptions is one of the reasons why Levitt put forward that rule. Tic-Tac-Toe is a game of skill. It just so happens that the skill level required to play perfectly is low and easy to achieve. Play it against a 5 year old who's never played before and you'll see how your skill is greater than theirs.
Blackjack is also not an exception, but looks to be because:
- the edge created by having greater skill at the highest level is almost non-existent when playing against similarly skilled opponents;
- the edge against the house is so small, even playing at the highest skill level. When you add the rake (or whatever the house takings are called for Blackjack), the edge is all but eliminated.
But these things don't make the skill component disappear.
Thanks for the post, it made me think.
The thing about Andrew also is, if he is available at 16, you have reason to believe that your scouting department may be wrong. Of the 7 teams with a chance, NONE took it. And, given that he didn't go in the top 8. It's pretty likely that you have him rated higher than everybody else.
Jase,
I guess it's where you draw the line. In a sense, playing the lottery requires skill, because you have to know how to bubble in the numbers, or even just hand the clerk the money and ask for your ticket.
Usually, when you talk about competitions, you're talking about how much skill affects the results. For lottery tickets, every competitor has the same skill to say "one ticket, please". For tic-tac-toe, it's everyone over five-year-olds. For blackjack, it's every serious player.
In practice, you're usually dealing with a *real life* level of competition. Such as, serious everyday players. And, for blackjack, lotteries, and tic-tac-toe, serious players all have achieved the natural limit of skill, so, from there, the competition's outcome is all determined by luck (or, in the case of tic-tac-toe, the equilibrium).
In the comments of that post one person makes the point that you actually can lose at the lottery on purpose. He makes the point with roulette. If you always make a bet on all the numbers in roulette you will always lose. If you bet on all combinations in the lottery you will always lose, unless the jackpot is already greater than the cost of covering all combinations. But at that point playing the lottery is actually starts to cross the line to skill. If a sufficient jackpot is available the confounding factor is splitting the jackpot.
Progressive jackpots also make Slots a game of skill. You can play in a way that makes your expected gain positive, but if you don't follow the correct strategies (not betting such that your bet can win the progressive prize) your expected gain can still be negative.
This reminds me of a section of AntiFragile by Nassim Taleb, where he discusses the theory of "Via Negativa". Benefit from removal (via negativa), often has a larger upside then benefit by addition (via positiva). This idea applies to many areas of life, including health/wellness, money management and work.
Interesting and correlated ideas. A very insightful article.
"If you don't like that one, try casino blackjack. You can lose on purpose just by hitting every hand -- eventually, you'll go over 21 and bust. But, can you *win* on purpose? Only to a certain limit. "
That limit is imposed by the specific casino rules, which determines the casino edge. Take any skillful game you want, charge a large enough vig (casino edge) and you could turn that skillful game into a game where you can't win.
I was directed to this page from an article about Dusty Baker being fired from the Reds. Interesting article. The couple people who were being somewhat critical, you both were really reaching...you just couldn't sit there and say nothing, you just had to say something!
Post a Comment
<< Home